Nozick’s Lockean digression

As we mentioned at the end of our previous post, smack dab in the middle of one of the most original and mind-blowing thought experiments in the history of political philosophy, Nozick digresses to discuss Locke’s views on parental ownership of children. Although the ostensible reason for this Lockean digression is to figure out whether children are to be included in Nozick’s imaginary “one-shareholder, one vote” scheme, we suspect that the true reason for tucking this digression away in this part of the book might be a more sinister one: to conceal some serious internal contradictions in Locke’s labor theory of property rights.

Why would Nozick want to conceal, or at least minimize, these internal contradictions? Because the entire edifice of Nozick’s entitlement theory of justice in general and his defense of the minimal state in particular are built on Lockean foundations. Specifically, Nozick’s entitlement theory is premised on Locke’s sweat-equity theory of property. According to Locke, the ultimate source of property rights is one’s labor. Locke’s axiom is that one is entitled to (i.e. has a natural property right to) the fruits of one’s labors. The general idea is this: if you make something out of materials you already own or are otherwise entitled to use, then it’s yours. But what about children? Are children to be included in Locke’s conception of property-rights acquisition? After all, to the extent parents biologically “make” their children and expend a lot of time and effort in rearing them, the Lockean conclusion is inescapable: parents must therefore own their children. Locke, however, rejects this conclusion out of hand and gives at least two possible reasons why parents don’t own their own children:

  • Argument #1. According to Nozick (p. 288), Locke’s “major argument [against parental ownership of children] seems to depend upon the view that one owns something one makes only if one controls and understands all parts of the process making it.” But this view of property rights is too restrictive, for as Nozick notes (ibid.), “By this criterion, people who plant seeds on their land and water them would not own trees that then grow,” unless they fully understood all the ins and outs of the process of photosynthesis.
  • Argument #2. Nozick quotes Locke’s second argument in full: “’Even the power which God himself exerciseth over mankind is by right of fatherhood, yet this fatherhood is such a one as utterly excludes all pretense of title in earthly parents; for he is King because he is indeed maker of us all, which no parents can pretend to be of their own children.’” Yet, however this broad and untestable claim is interpreted, it too undermines Locke’s labor theory of property. In the words of Nozick (p. 288):

“If the point is that people cannot own their children because they themselves are owned [by God] and so incapable of ownership, this would apply to owning everything else they make as well. If the point is that God, far more than a child’s parents, is the maker of a child, this applies to many other things that Locke thinks can be owned (plants, nonhuman animals [and land]); and perhaps it applies to everything.”

In other words, not only are Locke’s arguments unpersuasive and untestable; those arguments also have the unintended effect of undermining his own sweat-equity conception of property rights! Nevertheless, Nozick (like Locke) is not prepared to concede that parents own their children. Even in his imaginary “one-shareholder, one vote” world, a world in which human corporations are eventually consolidated into one “Great Corporation,” Nozick ends up stipulating (on page 289 of ASU) that children will be allowed to decide for themselves (presumably upon reaching the age of majority) whether they wish to join this collective corporate entity. But this concession now poses a new problem: holdouts. Specifically, how should the Great Corporation deal with persons who refuse to participate in this grand scheme? We will address the holdout problem in our next post.

Image result for self-refuting
This entry was posted in Uncategorized. Bookmark the permalink.

2 Responses to Nozick’s Lockean digression

  1. Kathy H says:

    Locke’s arguments seem absurd to me because God is man made. Look at all the variations of religion. Man would own God. Would a better argument be you have to have the mental capacity to join the Corporation and a child would not have that capacity. The child would automatically be included in the Corporation, but the parent would have the proxy to vote for the child.

    • Excellent point. The ownership issue is a red herring, i.e. irrelevant to the question of membership in the imaginary “great corporation,” since we can address the child issue on other grounds, such as mental capacity. I am now more convinced that Nozick is burying Locke’s arguments re: children here to minimize the internal contradictions in Locke’s labor theory of property.

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google+ photo

You are commenting using your Google+ account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s